This e-text of Henry Hazlitt's 1964 "The Foundations of Morality" is made available by the The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty. | |
Chapter 1: Introduction
Like many another writer, Herbert Spencer wrote his own first
book on morals, The Data of Ethics, under a sense of urgency.
In the preface to that volume, in June 1879, he told his readers
that he was departing from the order originally set down for the
volumes in his "System of Synthetic Philosophy" because:
"Hints, repeated of late years with increasing frequency
and distinctness, have shown me that health may permanently fail,
even if life does not end, before I reach the last part of the
task I have marked out for myself."
"This last part of the task it is," he continued, "to
which I regard all the preceding parts as subsidiary." And
he went on to say that ever since his first essay in 1842, on
The Proper Sphere of Government, "my ultimate purpose,
lying behind all proximate purposes, has been that of finding
for the principles of right and wrong, in conduct at large, a
scientific basis."
Moreover, he regarded the establishment of rules of right conduct
on a scientific basis as "a pressing need. Now that moral
injunctions are losing the authority given by their supposed sacred
origin, the secularization of morals is becoming imperative. Few
things can happen more disastrous than the decay and death of
a regulative system no longer fit, before another and fitter regulative
system has grown up to replace it. Most of those who reject the
current creed appear to assume that the controlling agency furnished
by it may safely be thrown aside, and the vacancy left unfilled
by any other controlling agency. Meanwhile, those who defend the
current creed allege that in the absence of the guidance it yields,
no guidance can exist: divine commandments they think the only
possible guides."
Spencer's fears of more than eighty years ago have been in large
part realized, and at least partly for the reason he gave. Along
with the decline of religious faith since his day, there has been
a decline in morality. It is seen almost throughout the world
in the increase of crime, in the rise of juvenile delinquency,
in the increasing resort to violence for the settlement of internal
economic and political disputes, in the decline of authority and
discipline. Above all, and in its most extreme form, it is seen
in the rise of Communism, that "religion of immoralism,"
(1) both as a doctrine and a world political force.
Now the contemporary decline in morality is at least in part the
result of the decline in religion. There are probably millions
of people who believe, with Ivan Karamazov in Dostoyevsky's novel,
that under atheism "everything is permissible." And
many would even say, with his half-brother Smerdyakov, who
took him with tragic literalness, that "If there's no everlasting
God, there's no such thing as virtue, and there's no need of it."
Marxism is not only belligerently atheistic, but seeks to destroy
religion precisely because it believes it to be "the opium
of the people" -- i.e., because it supports a "bourgeois"
morality that deprecates the systematic deceit, lying, treachery,
lawlessness, confiscation, violence, civil war, and murder that
the Communists regard as necessary for the overthrow or conquest
of capitalism.
How far religious faith may be a necessary basis of ethics we
shall examine at a later point. Here I wish merely to point out
that historically at least a large part of ethical rules and customs
have always had a secular basis. And this is true not only of
moral customs but of philosophical ethics. It is merely necessary
to mention the names of such pre-Christian moralists as Confucius,
Pythagoras, Heraclitus, Democritus, Socrates, Plato, Aristotle,
and the Stoics and Epicureans, to recall the extent to which this
is true. Even the churchmen of the Middle Ages, as represented
pre-eminently by Thomas Aquinas, were indebted for more of
their ethical theory to Aristotle than to Augustine.
2. A Practical Problem
But granted that moral custom and moral theory can have an autonomous
or partly autonomous base apart from any specific religious faith,
what is this base, and how is it to be found? This is the central
problem of philosophic ethics. As Schopenhauer has summed it up:
"To preach morality is easy, to give it a foundation is hard."
It is so very hard, indeed, as to seem almost hopeless. This sense
of near hopelessness has received eloquent expression from one
of the great ethical leaders of our century, Albert Schweitzer:
Is there, however, any sense in ploughing for the thousand and second time a field which has already been ploughed a thousand and one times? Has not everything which can be said about ethics already been said by Lao-tse, Confucius, the Buddha, and Zarathustra; by Amos and Isaiah; by Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle; by Epicurus and the Stoics; by Jesus and Paul; by the thinkers of the Renaissance, of the "Aufklarung," and of Rationalism; by Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hume; by Spinoza and Kant; by Fichte and Hegel; by Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and others? Is there any possibility of getting beyond all these contradictory convictions of the past to new beliefs which will have a stronger and more lasting influence? Can the ethical kernel of the thoughts of all these men be collected into an idea of the ethical, which will unite all the energies to which they appeal? We must hope so, if we are not to despair of the fate of the human race. (2)
It would seem enormously presumptuous, after this list of great
names, for anyone to write still another book on ethics, if it
were not for two considerations: first, ethics is primarily a
practical problem; and secondly, it is a problem that has
not yet been satisfactorily solved.
It is no disparagement of ethics to recognize frankly that the
problems it poses are primarily practical. If they were not practical
we would be under no obligation to solve them. Even Kant, one
of the most purely theoretical of theoreticians, recognized the
essentially practical nature of ethical thinking in the very title
of his chief work on ethics: Critique of Practical Reason.
If we lose sight of this practical goal, the first danger is that
we may lose ourselves in unanswerable questions such as: What
are we here for? What is the purpose of the existence of the universe?
What is the ultimate destiny of mankind? The second danger is
that we may fall into mere triviality and dilettantism, and end
up with some such conclusion as that of C. D. Broad: "We can no more learn to act rightly by appealing to the ethical theory of right action than we can play golf well by appealing to the mathematical theory of the golf-ball. The interest of ethics is thus almost wholly theoretical, as is the interest of the mathematical theory of golf or of billiards.... Salvation is not everything; and to try to understand in outline what one solves ambulando in detail is quite good fun for those people who like that sort of thing." (3)
Such an attitude tends toward sterility. It leads one to select
the wrong problems as the most important, and it gives no standard
for testing the usefulness of a conclusion. It is because so many
ethical writers have taken a similar attitude that they have been
so often lost in purely verbal problems and so often satisfied
with merely rhetorical solutions. One can imagine how little progress
would have been made in law reform, jurisprudence, or economics
if they had been thought of as posing purely theoretical problems
that were merely "good fun for those people who like that
sort of thing."
The present fashionable disparagement of "mere practicality"
was not shared by Immanuel Kant, who pointed out that: "To
yield to every whim of curiosity, and to allow our passion for
inquiry to be restrained by nothing but the limits of our ability,
this shows an eagerness of mind not unbecoming to scholarship.
But it is wisdom that has the merit of selecting, from among
the innumerable problems which present themselves, those whose
solution is important to mankind." (4)
But the progress of philosophical ethics has not been disappointing
merely because so many writers have lost sight of its ultimately
practical aims. It has been retarded also by the over hastiness
of some leading writers to be "original" -- to make
over ethics entirely at one stroke; to be new Lawgivers, competing
with Moses; to "transvalue all values" with Nietzsche;
or to seize, like Bentham, on some single, oversimplified test,
like Pleasure-and-Pain, or the Greatest Happiness, and
to begin applying it in much too direct and sweeping a manner
to all traditional ethical judgments, dismissing with short shrift
all those that do not immediately seem to conform with the New
Revelation.
3. Is It a Science?
We are likely to make more solid progress, I think, if we are
not at the beginning too hasty or too ambitious. I shall not undertake
in this book a lengthy discussion of the vexed question whether
ethics is or can be a "science." It is enough to point
out here that the word "science" is used today with
a wide range of meanings, and that the struggle to apply it to
every branch of inquiry or study, or to every theory, is chiefly
a struggle for prestige, and an attempt to ascribe precision and
certainty to one's conclusions. I will content myself here with
pointing out that ethics is not a science in the sense in which
that word is applied to the physical sciences -- to the determination
of matters of objective fact, or to the establishment of scientific
laws which enable us to make exact predictions. But ethics is
entitled to be called a science if we mean by this a systematic
inquiry conducted by rational rules. It is not a mere chaos. It
is not just a matter of opinion, in which one person's opinion
is as good as another's, or in which one statement is as true
or as false or as "meaningless" or as unverifiable as
another; in which neither rational induction nor deduction nor
the principles of investigation or logic play any part. If by
science, in short, we mean simply rational inquiry aiming to arrive
at a unified and systematized body of deductions and conclusions,
then ethics is a science. Ethics bears the same relation to psychology and praxeology (the general theory of human action) as medicine bears to physiology and pathology and as engineering bears to physics and mechanics. It is of little importance whether we call medicine, engineering or ethics an applied science, a normative science, or a scientific art. The function of each is to deal in a systematic way with a class of problems that need to be solved. Whether ethics is or is not to be called a science is, as I have hinted above, largely a semantic problem, a struggle to raise or lower its prestige and the seriousness with which it should be taken. But the answer we give has important practical consequences. These who insist on its right to the title, and use the word "science" in its narrower sense, are likely not only to claim for their conclusions an unchangeable inflexibility and certainty, but to follow pseudo-scientific methods in an effort to imitate physics. Those who deny ethics the title in any form are likely to conclude (or have already concluded) either that ethical problems are meaningless and unanswerable and that "might is right," or, on the other hand, that they already know all the answers by "intuition," or a "moral sense," or direct revelation from God. Let us agree, then, provisionally, that ethics is at least one of the "moral sciences" (in the sense in which John Stuart Mill used the word) and that if it is not a "science" in the exact and narrower sense it is at least a "discipline"; it is at least a branch of systematized knowledge or study; it is at least what the Germans call a Wissenschaft. (5) What is the aim of this science? What is the task before us? What are the questions we are trying to answer? Let us begin with the more modest aims and move on to the more ambitious. Our most modest aim is to find out what our unwritten moral code actually is, what our traditional, "spontaneous," or "common sense" moral judgments actually are. Our next aim must be to ask to what extent these judgments form a consistent whole. Wherever they are inconsistent, or apparently so, we must look for some principle or criterion that would harmonize them or decide between them. After twenty-five hundred years and thousands of books, it is enormously probable that no completely "original" theory of ethics is possible. Probably all the leading major principles have been at least suggested. Progress in ethics is likely to consist, rather, in more definiteness, precision, and clarification, in harmonization, in more generality and unification. A "system" of ethics, therefore, would mean a code, or a set of principles, that formed a consistent, coherent, and integrated whole. But in order to arrive at this coherence, we must seek the ultimate criterion by which acts or rules of action have been or should be tested. We shall be inevitably led to this merely by trying to make explicit what was merely implicit, by trying to make consistent, rules that were inconsistent, by trying to make definite or precise, rules or judgments that were vague or loose, by trying to unify what was separate and to complete what was partial. And when and if we find this basic moral criterion, this test of right and wrong, we may indeed find ourselves obliged to revise at least some of our former moral judgments, and to re-value at least some of our former values.
1. See Max Eastman's chapter with that title in his Reflections on the Failure of Socialism (New York: Devin-Adair, 1955). 2. The Philosophy of Civilization (New York: Macmillan, 1957), p. 103. 3. Five Types of Ethical Theory (New York, Harcourt Brace, 1930), p. 285. 4. Dreams of a Ghost Seer, Part II, Chap. III (Werke, ed. E. Cassirer, Vol. 11, p. 385). See also Karl R. Popper, The Poverty of Historicism (Boston: Beacon Press, 1957), pp. 55-58. 5. See Fritz Machlup, "The Inferiority Complex of the Social Sciences" in On Freedom and Free Enterprise, ed. Mary Sennholz (Princeton: Van Nostrand, 1956). Morris R. Cohen, Reason and Nature (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1931; Glencoe, 111.: Free Press, 1953), p. 89. John Stuart Mill, "On the Logic of the Moral Sciences," A System of Logic, Vol. II, Book VI. © 1964 Henry Hazlitt. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533. Jamie Hazlitt 45 Division St S1 4GE Sheffield, UK +44 114 275 6539 contact@hazlitt.org, / |