This e-text of Henry Hazlitt's 1964 "The Foundations of Morality" is made available by the The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty. | |
Chapter 3: The Moral Criterion
Speculative thought comes late in the history of mankind. Men
act before they philosophize about their actions. They learned
to talk, and developed language, ages before they developed any
interest in grammar or linguistics. They worked and saved, planted
crops, fashioned tools, built homes, owned, bartered, bought and
sold, and developed money, long before they formulated any explicit
theories of economics. They developed forms of government and
law, and even judges and courts, before they formulated theories
of politics or jurisprudence. And they acted implicitly in accordance
with a code of morals, rewarded or punished, approved or disapproved
of the actions of their fellows in adhering to or violating that
code of morals, long before it even occurred to them to inquire
into the rationale of what they were doing.
It would seem at first glance both natural and logical, therefore,
to begin the study of ethics with an inquiry into the history
or evolution of ethical practice and judgments. Certainly we should
engage in such an inquiry at some time in the course of our study.
Yet ethics is perhaps the one discipline where it seems more profitable
to begin at the other end. For ethics is a "normative"
science. It is not a science of description, but of prescription.
It is not a science of what is or was, but of what ought to
be.
True, it would have no claim to scientific validity, or even any
claim to be a useful field of inquiry, unless it were based in
some convincing way on what was or what is. But here we have stepped
into the very center of an age-old controversy. Many ethical writers
have contended during the last two centuries that "no accumulation
of observed sequences, no experience of what is, no predictions
of what will be, can possibly prove what ought to be."
(1)
And others have even gone on to assert that there is no
way of getting from an is to an ought.
If the latter statement were true, there would be no possibility
of framing a rational theory of ethics. Unless our oughts are
to be purely arbitrary, purely dogmatic, they must somehow grow
out of what is.
Now the connection between what is and what ought to be is always
a desire of some kind. We recognize this in our daily decisions.
When we are trying to decide on a course of action, and are asking
advice, we are told, for example: "If you desire to become
a doctor, you must go to medical school. If you desire to get
ahead, you must be diligent in your business. If you don't want
to get fat, you must watch your diet. If you want to avoid lung
cancer, you must cut down on cigarettes," etc. The generalized
form of such advice may be reduced to this:. If you desire to
attain a certain end, you ought to use a certain means,
because this is the means most likely to achieve it. The is
the desire; the ought is the means of gratifying it.
So far, so good. But how far does this get us toward a theory
of ethics? For if a man does not desire an end, there seems no
way of convincing him that he ought to pursue the means to that
end. If a man prefers the certainty of getting fat, or the risk
of a heart attack, to curbing his appetite or giving up his favorite
delicacies; if he prefers the risks of lung cancer to giving up
smoking, any ought based on the assumption of a contrary
preference loses its force.
A story so old that it is told as an old one even by Bentham (2) is that of the oculist and the sot: A countryman who had hurt his eyes by drinking went to a celebrated oculist for advice.
He found him at table, with a glass of wine before him. "You
must leave off drinking," said the oculist. "How so?"
says the countryman. "You don't, and yet methinks your own
eyes are none of the best." -- "That's very true, friend,"
replied the oculist: "but you are to know, I love my bottle
better than my eyes."
How, then, do we move from any basis of desire to any theory of
ethics?
We find the solution when we take a longer and broader view. All
our desires may be generalized as desires to substitute a more
satisfactory state of affairs for a less satisfactory state. It
is true that an individual, under the immediate influence of impulse
or passion, of a moment of anger or rage, malice, vindictiveness,
or the desire for revenge, or gluttony, or an overwhelming craving
for a release of sexual tension, or for a smoke or a drink or
a drug, may in the long run only reduce a more satisfactory state
to a less satisfactory state, may make himself less happy rather
than more happy. But this less satisfactory state was not his
real conscious intention even at the moment of acting. He realizes,
in retrospect, that his action was folly; he did not improve his
condition, but made it worse; he did not act in accordance with
his long-run interests, but against them. He is always willing
to recognize, in his calmer moments, that he should choose the
action that best promotes his own interests and maximizes his
own happiness (or minimizes his own unhappiness) in the long
run. Wise and disciplined men refuse to indulge in immediate
pleasures when the indulgence seems only too likely to lead in
the long run to an overbalance of misery or pain.
To repeat and to sum up: It is not true that "no amount of
is can make an ought." The ought rests, in
fact, and must rest, either upon an is or upon a will be. The
sequence is simple: Every man, in his cool and rational moments,
seeks his own long-run happiness. This is a fact; this
is an is. Mankind has found, over the centuries that certain
rules of action best tend to promote the long-run happiness of
both the individual and society. These rules of action have come
to be called moral rules. Therefore, assuming that one
seeks one's long-run happiness, these are the rules one ought
to follow.
Certainly this is the whole basis of what is called prudential
ethics. In fact, wisdom, or the art of living wisely, is perhaps
only another name for prudential ethics.
Prudential ethics constitutes a very large part of all ethics.
But the whole of ethics rests upon the same foundation. For men
find that they best promote their own interests in the long run
not merely by refraining from injury to their fellows, but by
cooperating with them. Social cooperation is the foremost means
by which the majority of us attain most of our ends. It is on
the implicit if not the explicit recognition of this that our
codes of morals, our rules of conduct, are ultimately based. "Justice"
itself (as we shall later see more clearly) consists in observance
of the rules or principles that do most, in the long run, to preserve
and promote social cooperation.
We shall find also, when we have explored the subject further,
that there are no irreconcilable conflicts between egoism and
altruism, between selfishness and benevolence, between the long-run
interests of the individual and those of society. In most cases
in which such conflicts appear to exist, the appearance exists
because only short-run consequences, and not consequences over
the long run, are being taken into consideration.
Social cooperation is, of course, itself a means. It is a means
to the never completely attainable goal of maximizing the happiness
and well-being of mankind. But the great difficulty of making
the latter our direct goal is the lack of unanimity in the tastes,
ends, and value judgments of individuals. An activity that gives
one man pleasure may be a great bore to another. "One man's
meat is another man's poison." But social cooperation is
the great means by which we all help each other to attain our
individual ends, and so to attain the ends of "society."
Moreover, we do share a great number of basic ends in common;
and social cooperation is the principal means of attaining these
also.
In brief, the aim of each of us to satisfy his own desires, to
achieve as far as possible his own highest happiness and well-being,
is best forwarded by a common means, Social Cooperation, and cannot
be achieved without that means.
Here, then, is the foundation on which we may build a rational
system of ethics.
1. Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil (London: Oxford University Press, 1907), I, 53. 2. Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1823), p. 319n. © 1964 Henry Hazlitt. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533. Jamie Hazlitt 45 Division St S1 4GE Sheffield, UK +44 114 275 6539 contact@hazlitt.org, / |