Chapter 25: On Appeasing Envy(*)
Any attempt to equalize wealth or income by forced
redistribution must only tend to destroy wealth and income. Historically the
best the would-be equalizers have ever succeeded in doing is to equalize
downward. This has even been caustically described as their intention.
"Your levellers," said Samuel Johnson in the mid-eighteenth century,
"wish to level down as far as themselves; but they cannot bear
levelling up to themselves." And in our own day we find even an eminent
liberal like the late Mr. Justice Holmes writing: "I have no respect for
the passion for equality, which seems to me merely idealizing envy." (1)
At least a handful of writers have begun to recognize
explicitly the all-pervasive role played by envy or the fear of envy in life and
in contemporary political thought. In 1966, Helmut Schoeck, professor of
sociology at the University of Mainz, devoted a penetrating book to the subject. (2)
There can be little doubt that many egalitarians are
motivated at least partly by envy, while still others are motivated, not so much
by any envy of their own, as by the fear of it in others, and the wish to
appease or satisfy it.
But the latter effort is bound to be futile. Almost no one is
completely satisfied with his status in relation to his fellows. In the envious
the thirst for social advancement is insatiable. As soon as they have risen one
rung in the social or economic ladder, their eyes are fixed upon the next. They
envy those who are higher up, no matter by how little. In fact, they are more
likely to envy their immediate friends or neighbors, who are just a little bit
better off, than celebrities or millionaires who are incomparably better off.
The position of the latter seems unattainable, but of the neighbor who has just
a minimal advantage they are tempted to think: "I might almost be in his
place."
Moreover, the envious are more likely to be mollified by
seeing others deprived of some advantage than by gaining it for themselves. It
is not what they lack that chiefly troubles them, but what others have. The
envious are not satisfied with equality; they secretly yearn for superiority and
revenge. In the French revolution of 1848, a woman coal-heaver is reported to
have remarked to a richly dressed lady: "Yes, madam, everything's going to
be equal now; I shall go in silks and you'll carry coal."
Envy is implacable. Concessions merely whet its appetite for
more concessions. As Schoeck writes: "Man's envy is at its most intense
where all are almost equal; his calls for redistribution are loudest when there
is virtually nothing to redistribute." (3)
(We should, of course, always distinguish that merely
negative envy which begrudges others their advantage from the positive ambition
that leads men to active emulation, competition, and creative effort of their
own.)
But the accusation of envy, or even of the fear of others'
envy, as the dominant motive for any redistribution proposal, is a serious one
to make and a difficult if not impossible one to prove. Moreover, the motives
for making a proposal, even if ascertainable, are irrelevant to its inherent
merits.
We can, nonetheless, apply certain objective tests. Sometimes
the motive of appeasing other people's envy is openly avowed. Socialists will
often talk as if some form of superbly equalized destitution were preferable to
"maldistributed" plenty. A national income that is rapidly growing in
absolute terms for practically every one will be deplored because it is making
the rich richer. An implied and sometimes avowed principle of the British Labor
Party leaders after World War II was that "Nobody should have what
everybody can't have."
Equality, Yes; Abundance, No!
But the main objective test of a social proposal is not
merely whether it emphasizes equality more than abundance, but whether it goes
further and attempts to promote equality at the expense of abundance. Is the
proposed measure intended primarily to help the poor, or to penalize the rich?
And would it in fact punish the rich at the cost of also hurting everyone else?
This is the actual effect, as we saw earlier, (4) of steeply progressive income taxes and confiscatory inheritance
taxes. These are not only counter-productive fiscally (bringing in less revenue
from the higher brackets than lower rates would have brought), but they
discourage or confiscate the capital accumulation and investment that would have
increased national productivity and real wages. Most of the confiscated funds
are then dissipated by the government in current consumption expenditures. The
long-run effect of such tax rates, of course, is to leave the working poor worse
off than they would otherwise have been.
There are economists who will admit all this, but will answer
that it is nonetheless politically necessary to impose such near-confiscatory
taxes, or to enact similar re-distributive measures, in order to placate the
dissatisfied and the envious -- in order, even, to prevent actual revolution.
Appeasement Provokes Envy
This argument is the reverse of the truth. The effect of
trying to appease envy is to provoke more of it.
The most popular theory of the French Revolution is that it
came about because the economic condition of the masses was becoming worse and
worse, while the king and the aristocracy remained completely blind to it. But
Tocqueville, one of the most penetrating social observers and historians of his
or any time, put forward an exactly opposite explanation. Let me state it first
as summarized by an eminent French commentator in 1899:
Here is the theory invented by Tocqueville.... The lighter a yoke, the more
it seems insupportable; what exasperates is not the crushing burden but the
impediment; what inspires to revolt is not oppression but humiliation. The
French of 1789 were incensed against the nobles because they were almost the
equals of the nobles; it is the slight difference that can be appreciated, and
what can be appreciated that counts. The eighteenth-century middle class was
rich, in a position to fill almost any employment, almost as
powerful as the nobility. It was exasperated by this "almost" and
stimulated by the proximity of its goal; impatience is always provoked by the
final strides. (5)
I have quoted this passage because I do not find the theory stated in quite this condensed form by Tocqueville himself. Yet this is essentially the theme of his L'Ancien Regime et la Revolution, and he presented impressive factual documentation to support it.
As the prosperity which I have just described began to extend in France, the community nevertheless became more unsettled and uneasy; public discontent grew fierce; hatred against all established institutions increased. The nation was visibly advancing toward a revolution.
It might be said that the French found their position the more intolerable
precisely where it had become better. Surprising as this fact is, history is
full of such contradictions.
It is not always by going from bad to worse that a country
falls into revolution. It happens most frequently that a people, which had
supported the most crushing laws without complaint, and apparently as if they
were unfelt, throws them off with violence as soon as the burden begins to be
diminished. The state of things destroyed by a revolution is almost always
somewhat better than that which immediately preceded it; and experience has
shown that the most dangerous moment for a bad government is usually that when
it enters upon the work of reform. Nothing short of great political genius can
save a sovereign who undertakes to relieve his subjects after a long period of
oppression. The evils which were endured with patience so long as they were
inevitable seem intolerable as soon as a hope can be entertained of escaping
from them. The abuses which are removed seem to lay bare those which remain,
and to render the sense of them more acute; the evil has decreased, it is
true, but the perception of the evil is more keen....
No one any longer contended in 1780 that France was in a state of decline;
there seemed, on the contrary, to be just then no bounds to her progress. Then
it was that the theory of the continual and indefinite perfectibility of man
took its origin. Twenty years before nothing was to be hoped of the future:
then nothing was to be feared. The imagination, grasping at this near and
unheard of felicity, caused men to overlook the advantages they already
possessed, and hurried them forward to something new. (6)
Aggravated by Sympathy
The expressions of sympathy that came from the privileged
class itself only aggravated the situation:
The very men who had most to fear from the fury of the people declaimed loudly
in their presence on the cruel injustice under which the people had always
suffered. They pointed out to each other the monstrous vices of those
institutions which had weighed most heavily upon the lower orders: they
employed all their powers of rhetoric in depicting the miseries of the common
people and their un-paid labor; and thus they infuriated while they endeavored
to relieve them. (7)
Tocqueville went on to quote at length from the mutual
recriminations of the king, the nobles, and the parliament in blaming each other
for the wrongs of the people. To read them now is to get the uncanny feeling
that they are plagiarizing the rhetoric of the limousine liberals of our own
day.
All this does not mean that we should refrain from taking any
measure truly calculated to relieve hardship and reduce poverty. What it does
mean is that we should never take governmental measures merely for the purpose
of trying to assuage the envious or appease the agitators, or to buy off a
revolution. Such measures, betraying weakness and a guilty conscience, only lead
to more far-reaching and even ruinous demands. A government that pays social
blackmail will precipitate the very consequences that it fears.
Notes
* This article, a chapter in Hazlitt's book, The Conquest of Poverty, published by Arlington House, appeared in the March 1972 issue of The Freeman.
1. The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J.
Laski (ed. M. De Wolfe Howe, 2 vol., Cambridge, Mass. 1953). From Holmes to Laski, May 12, 1927, P. 942.
2. Helmut Schoeck, Envy (English translation, Harcourt, Brace & World, 1969).
3. Ibid., p. 303.
4. "Should We Divide the Wealth?" in The Freeman, February, 1972, p. 100.
5. Emile Faguet, Politicians and Moralists of the
Nineteenth Century (Boston: Little, Brown; 1928), p. 93.
6. Alexis de Tocqueville, On the State of Society in
France before the Revolution of 1789. London: John Murray, 1856, pp.
321-324. Also available as The Old Regime and the French Revolution in a Doubleday paperback.
7. Ibid., pp. 329-330.
"Wisdom of Henry Hazlitt" Home Page |
Next Chapter
This e-text is made available by The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty.
© 19XX. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533.
The Henry Hazlitt Foundation
Jamie Hazlitt
45 Division St
S1 4GE Sheffield, UK
+44 114 275 6539
contact@hazlitt.org, /
|