This e-text of Henry Hazlitt's 1964 "The Foundations of Morality" is made available by the The Henry Hazlitt Foundation in cooperation with The Foundation for Economic Education. The Hazlitt Foundation is a member-supported 501(c)(3) non-profit corporation whose mission is to make the ideas of freedom more accessible. Please visit our flagship Internet service Free-Market.Net: The world's most comprehensive source for information on liberty. | |
Chapter 5: Satisfaction and Happiness
The modern doctrine of eudaemonic ethics is differently framed.
It is customarily stated, not in terms of pleasures and pains,
but in terms of desires and satisfactions. Thus it bypasses some
of the psychological and verbal controversies raised by the older
pleasure-pain theories. (1) As we saw in Chapter 3 (p. 12), all our
desires may be generalized as desires to substitute a more satisfactory
state of affairs for a less satisfactory state. A man acts, in
Locke's phrase, because he feels some "uneasiness" and tries as far as possible to remove this uneasiness.
I shall argue in this chapter, therefore, in defense of at least
one form of the doctrine of "psychological eudaemonism."
Superficially similar doctrines, under the name "psychological
hedonism" or "psychological egoism," are actively
opposed by many modern moral philosophers. We shall consider here
the criticism offered by an older moral philosopher, Hastings
Rashdall.
Rashdall, criticizing "psychological hedonism," held
that it rested on a great "hysteron-proteron" -- an
inversion of the true order of logical dependence, a reversal
of cause and effect: "The fact that a thing is desired no doubt implies that the satisfaction of the desire will necessarily bring pleasure. There is undoubtedly pleasure in the satisfaction of all desire. But that is a very different thing from asserting that the object is desired because it is thought of as pleasant, and in proportion as it is thought of as pleasant. The hedonistic Psychology involves, according to the stock phrase, a "hysteron-proteron"; it puts the cart before the horse. In reality, the imagined pleasantness is created by the desire, not the desire by the imagined pleasantness. " (2)
But in making this criticism, Rashdall was forced to concede something --
the fact that men actually do seek satisfaction of their desires,
whatever these desires happen to be. "The gratification of
every desire necessarily gives pleasure in actual fact, and is
consequently conceived of as pleasant in idea before the desire
is accomplished. That is the truth which lies at the bottom of
all the exaggerations and misrepresentations of the hedonistic
Psychology." (3)
And here we have a firmer positive basis than the older pleasure-pain
psychology on which we can build. As the German philosopher Friedrich
Heinrich Jacobi (1743-1819) declared: "We originally want
or desire an object not because it is agreeable or good, but we
call it agreeable or good because we want or desire it; and we
do this because our sensuous or supersensuous nature so requires.
There is, thus, no basis for recognizing what is good and worth
wishing for outside of the faculty of desiring -- i.e., the original
desire and the wish themselves ." (4) But all this was said
much earlier by Spinoza in his Ethics (Part 111, Prop.
IX): "In no case do we strive for, wish for, long for, or
desire anything because we deem it to be good, but on the other
hand we deem a thing to be good, because we strive for it, wish
for it, long for it, or desire it."
Bertrand Russell, whose opinions on ethics have undergone many
minor changes and at least one major revolution, has finally settled
on this view, as revealed in two books published nearly thirty
years apart. Let us begin with the earlier statement: "There is a view, advocated, e.g. by Dr. G. E. Moore, that "good" is an indefinable notion, and that we know a priori certain general propositions about the kinds of things that are good on their own account. Such things as happiness, knowledge, appreciation of beauty, are known to be good, according to Dr. Moore; it is also known that we ought to act so as to create what is good and prevent what is bad. I formerly held this view myself, but I was led to abandon it, partly by Mr. Santayana's Winds of Doctrine. I now think that good and bad are derivative from desire. I do not mean quite simply that the good is the desired, because men's desires conflict, and "good" is, to my mind, mainly a social concept, designed to find issue from this conflict. The conflict, however, is not only between the desires of different men, but between incompatible desires of one man at different times, or even at the same time." (5)
Russell then goes on to ask how the desires of a single individual
can be harmonized with each other, and how, if possible, the desires
of different individuals can be harmonized with each other.
In Human Society in Ethics and Politics, published in 1955,
he returns to the same theme: "I mean by "right" conduct that conduct which will probably produce the greatest balance of satisfaction over dissatisfaction, or the smallest balance of dissatisfaction over satisfaction, and that, in making this estimate, the question as to who enjoys the satisfaction, or suffers the dissatisfaction, is to be considered irrelevant .... I say "satisfaction" rather than "pleasure" or "interest." The term "interest" as commonly employed has too narrow a connotation .... The term "satisfaction" is wide enough to embrace everything that comes to a man through the realization of his desires, and these desires do not necessarily have any connection with self, except that one feels them. One may, for instance, desire -- I do myself -- that a proof should be discovered for Fermat's last theorem, and one may be glad if a brilliant young mathematician is given a sufficient grant to enable him to seek a proof. The gratification that one would feel in this case comes under the head of satisfaction, but hardly of self-interest as commonly understood. 2. "Happiness" or "Well-Being"? Thus codes of morals have their starting point in human desires,
choices, preferences, valuations. But the recognition of this,
important as it is, carries us only a little way towards the construction
of an ethical system or even a basis for evaluating existing ethical
rules and judgments.
We shall take up the next steps in succeeding chapters. But before
we come to these chapters, which will be mainly concerned with
the problem of means, let us ask whether we can frame any
satisfactory answer to the question of ends.
It will not do to say, as some modern moral philosophers have
been content to say, that ends are "pluralistic" and
wholly incommensurable. This evades entirely one of the most important
problems of ethics. The ethical problem as it presents itself
in practice in daily life is precisely which course of
action we "ought" to take, precisely which "end,"
among conflicting "ends," we ought to pursue.
It is frequently asserted by moral philosophers, for example,
that though "Happiness" may be an element in the ultimate
end, "Virtue" is also an ultimate end which cannot be
subsumed under or resolved into "Happiness." But suppose
a man is confronted with a decision in which one course of action,
in his opinion, would most tend to promote happiness (and not
necessarily or merely his own happiness but that of others) while
only a conflicting course of action would be most "virtuous"?
How can he resolve his problem? A rational decision can only be
made on some common basis of comparison. Either happiness is not
an ultimate end but rather a means to some further end, or virtue
is not an ultimate end but rather a means to some further end.
Either happiness must be valued in terms of its tendency to promote
virtue or virtue must be valued in terms of its tendency to promote
happiness, or both must be valued in terms of their tendency to
promote some further end beyond either.
One confusion that has stood in the way of solving this problem
has been the inveterate tendency of moral philosophers to draw
a sharp contrast between "means" and "ends,"
and then to assume that whatever can be shown to be a means to
some further end must be merely a means, and can have no
value "in itself," or, as they phrase it, can have no
"intrinsic" value.
Later we shall see in more detail that most things or values that
are the objects of human pursuit are both means and ends; that
one thing may be a means to a proximate end which in turn is a
means to some further end, which in turn may be a means to some
still further end; that these "means-ends" come to be
valued not only as means but as ends-in-themselves -- in other words,
acquire not only a derivative or "instrumental" value
but a quasi-"intrinsic" value.
But here we must state one of our provisional conclusions dogmatically.
At any moment we do not the thing that gives us most "pleasure"
(using the word in its usual connotation) but the thing that gives
us most satisfaction (or least dissatisfaction). If we act under
the influence of impulse or fear or anger or passion, we do the
thing that gives us most momentary satisfaction, regardless of
longer consequences. If we act calmly after reflection, we do
the thing we think likely to give us the most satisfaction (or
least dissatisfaction) in the long run. But when we judge our
actions morally (and especially when we judge the actions of others
morally), the question we ask or should ask is this: What
actions or rules of action would do most to promote the health,
happiness, and well-being in the long run of the individual agent,
or (if there is conflict) what rules of action would do most to
promote the health, happiness and well-being in the long run of
the whole community, or of all mankind?
I have used the long phrase "health, happiness, and wellbeing"
as the nearest equivalent to Aristotle's eudaemonia, which
seems to include all three. And I have used it because some moral
philosophers believe that Happiness, even if it means the long-run
happiness of mankind, is too narrow or too ignoble a goal. In
order to avoid barren disputes over words, I should be willing
to call the ultimate goal simply the Good, or Well-Being. There
could then be no objection on the ground that this ultimate goal,
this Summum Bonum, this criterion of all means or other
ends, was not made inclusive or noble enough. I have no strong
objection to the use of the term Well-Being to stand for
this ultimate goal, though I prefer the term Happiness, standing
by itself, as sufficiently inclusive, and yet more specific. But
wherever I use the word Happiness standing alone, any reader
may silently add and/or Well-Being, wherever he thinks
the addition is necessary to increase the comprehensiveness or
nobility of the goal.
3. Pleasure Cannot Be Quantified
Before leaving the subject of this chapter it seems desirable
to deal with some of the objections to the eudaemonic view that
it presents.
One of these has to do with the relations of desire to pleasure
-- the alleged "hysteron-proteron" fallacy mentioned at
the beginning of the chapter. I suspect that the people who place
most emphasis on this so-called fallacy are themselves guilty
of a confusion of thought. Their position is sometimes stated
in the form: "When I am hungry, I desire food, not pleasure."
But this statement depends for its persuasiveness upon an ambiguity
in the word "pleasure." If we substitute for "pleasure"
the term satisfaction the statement becomes a form of hairsplitting:
"When I am hungry I desire food, not the satisfaction of
my desire." What is involved here is not a contrast between
two different things, but merely between two different ways of
stating the same thing. The statement: "When I am hungry,
I desire food," is concrete and specific. The statement:
"I desire the satisfaction of my desires," is general
and abstract. There is no antithesis. Food in this example is
merely the specific means of satisfying a specific desire.
Yet since the time of Bishop Butler this point has been the subject
of bitter controversy. Both hedonists and anti-hedonists too commonly
forget that the word "pleasure," like the word "satisfaction,
" is merely an abstraction. A pleasure or satisfaction
does not exist apart from a specific pleasure or satisfaction.
"Pleasure" cannot be separated or isolated like a sort
of pure homogeneous juice from specific pleasures or sources of
pleasure.
Nor can pleasure be measured or quantified. Bentham's attempt
to quantify pleasure was ingenious, but a failure. How can one
measure the intensity of one pleasure, for example, against the
duration of another? Or the intensity of the "same"
pleasure against its duration? Precisely what decrease in intensity
is equal to precisely what increase in duration? If one answers
that the individual decides this whenever he makes a choice, then
one is saying that it is his subjective preference that
really counts, not the "quantity" of pleasure.
Pleasures and satisfactions can be compared in terms of more
or less, but they cannot be quantified. Thus we may
say that they are comparable, but we may not go on to say
that they are otherwise commensurable. We may say, for
example, that we prefer to go to the symphony tonight to playing
bridge, which is perhaps equivalent to saying that going to the
symphony tonight would give us more pleasure than playing bridge.
But we cannot meaningfully say that we prefer going to the symphony
tonight 3.72 times as much as playing bridge (or that it would
give us 3.72 times as much pleasure).
Thus even when we say that an individual is "trying to maximize
his satisfactions," we must be careful to keep in mind that
we are using the term "maximize" metaphorically. It
is an elliptical expression for "taking in each case the
action that seems to promise the most satisfying results."
We cannot legitimately use the term "maximize" in this
connection in the strict sense in which it is used in mathematics,
to imply the largest possible sum. Neither satisfactions
nor pleasures can be quantified. They can only be compared in
terms of more or less. To put the matter another
way, they can be compared ordinally, not cardinally. We can speak
of our first, second, and third choice. We can say that we expect
to get more satisfaction (or pleasure) from doing A than from
doing B, but we can never say precisely how much more.
(7)
4. Socrates and the Oyster
In comparing pleasures or satisfactions with each other, then,
it is legitimate to say that one is more or less than another,
but it is merely confusing to say with John Stuart Mill that one
is "higher" or "lower" than another. In this
respect Bentham was far more logical when he declared: "Quantity
of pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry." When,
trying to escape from this conclusion, Mill insisted that pleasures
should be measured by "quality . . . as well as quantity,"
(8) he was in effect abandoning pleasure itself as the standard
of guidance in conduct and appealing to some other and not clearly
specified standard. He was implying that we value states of consciousness
for some other reason than their pleasantness.
If we abandon the "pleasure" as the standard and substitute
satisfaction, it becomes clear that if the satisfaction that it
yields is the standard of conduct, and John Jones gets more satisfaction
from playing ping-pong than he does from reading poetry, then
he is justified in playing ping-pong. One may say, if one wishes,
again following Mill, that he would probably prefer poetry if
he had "experience of both." But this is far from certain.
It depends on what kind of person Jones is, on what his tastes
are, what his physical and mental capacities are, and his mood
of the moment. To insist that he should read poetry rather than
play ping-pong (even though the latter gives him intense pleasure
and the former would merely bore or irritate him), on the ground
that if he plays ping-pong and abjures poetry he will earn your
contempt, is to appeal to intellectual snobbery rather than to
morality.
In fact, Mill introduced a great deal of confusion of thought
into ethics when he wrote: "It is better to be a human being
dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied
than a fool satisfied. And if the fool, or the pig, are of a different
opinion, it is because they only know their side of the question.
The other party to the comparison knows both sides." (9)
Now it may be doubted that the other party to the comparison knows
both sides. An intelligent man has never been a pig, and does
not know precisely how a pig feels, or how he would feel if he
were a pig: he might then have a pig's preferences, whatever these
should turn out to be.
In any case, Mill has simply introduced an irrelevancy. He is
appealing to our snobbery, our pride, or our shame. No one who
reads philosophy at all would like to admit that he prefers to
be an ordinary man rather than a genius, let alone that he would
prefer being a pig to being an ordinary man. The reader is expected
to say, "A thousand times, no!"
But this does not happen to be the issue. If we stick to the issue,
then, we will reply: It is better to be Socrates satisfied than
Socrates dissatisfied. It is better to be a human being satisfied
than a human being dissatisfied. It is better to be a fool satisfied
than a fool dissatisfied. It is better even to be a pig satisfied
than a pig dissatisfied.
Each of these, if dissatisfied, is usually capable of taking some
action that would make him less dissatisfied. The actions that
would make him least dissatisfied in the long run, assuming they
were not at the expense of other persons (or pigs), would be the
most appropriate actions for him to take.
The choice of such actions is a real choice. The choice implied
by Mill is not. Neither a human being nor a pig, regardless of
his own desires, can change his animal status to that of the other.
Nor can a fool make himself into a Socrates simply by an act of
choice, nor Socrates into a fool. But human beings, at least,
are capable of choosing the actions that seem likely to bring
them most satisfaction in the long run.
If a moron is happy gaping at television but would be miserable
trying to read Plato or Mill or G. E. Moore, it would be cruel
and even stupid to try to force him to do the latter simply because
you think such reading would make a genius happy. It would hardly
be more "moral" for a commonplace man to torture or
bore himself by reading high-brow books rather than detective
stories if the latter gave him real pleasure. The moral life should
not be confused with the intellectual life. The moral life consists
in following the course that leads to the greatest long-run happiness
achievable by the individual concerned, and leads him to cooperate
with others to the extent of the capacities he actually has, rather
than those he might wish he had or might think he "ought"
to have. Yet this crypto-snobbish standard is appealed to again and again by moral philosophers. Bertrand Russell, in one of his many phases as a moral philosopher, once repeated, in effect, Plato's argument about the life of the oyster, having pleasure with no knowledge. Imagine such mindless pleasure, as intense and prolonged as you please, and would you choose it? Is it your good? And Santayana replied: "Here the British reader, like the blushing Greek youth, is expected to answer instinctively, No! It is an argumentum ad hominem (and there can be no other kind of argument in ethics); but the man who gives the required answer does so not because the answer is self-evident, which it is not, but because he is the required sort of man. He is shocked at the idea of resembling an oyster. Yet changeless pleasure, without memory or reflection, without the wearisome intermixture of arbitrary images, is just what the mystic, the voluptuary, and perhaps the oyster find to be good. . . . The impossibility which people labor under of being satisfied with pure pleasure as a goal is due to their want of imagination, or rather to their being dominated by an imagination which is exclusively human." (10) Let us carry Santayana's argument a step further. Let us assume that the moral philosopher asked: "Suppose you could get more pleasure, both immediately and in the long run, than you now get from witnessing the plays of Shakespeare, but without ever reading, seeing, or hearing a Shakespearian play, and remaining entirely ignorant of Shakespeare's work? Would you choose this greater pleasure?" Every lover of Shakespeare would probably answer No. But isn't this simply because he would not believe in the hypothetical choice? Because he simply could not imagine himself getting the pleasure of Shakespeare without reading or seeing Shakespearian plays? Pleasure can hardly be conceived as a pure abstraction apart from a particular pleasure. The antihedonist may reply in triumph that if people refuse to substitute one kind of pleasure for another, or one quality of pleasure for another, then they have made something else besides "quantity" of pleasure their test. But it should be pointed out to him that the test he applies to specific intellectual or specific "higher" pleasures could be applied, with the same kind of results, to specific sensual, carnal or "lower" pleasures. If the question were put to a voluptuary: "Suppose, by some other means, you could get more pleasure than you could get from sleeping with the most seductive woman in the world, but without having this latter privilege, would you choose this greater but disembodied pleasure?" Any lecher who was asked this question would probably also reply with an emphatic No. And the reason would be basically the same as for our Shakespeare lover. People cannot imagine or believe in a purely abstract pleasure, but only in a specific pleasure.
When a man is asked to imagine himself feeling pleasure,
though deprived of all his present sources of pleasure --
of all the things or activities that now bring him pleasure -- he
naturally finds himself unable to do it. It is like being asked
to imagine himself in love, but not with anybody.
The answer becomes clearer when we abandon the word "pleasure"
and substitute satisfaction. We do not ordinarily speak
of "quantity" of satisfaction, as we are tempted to
do with "pleasure," but only of greater or less
satisfaction. Nor do we speak of "quality" of satisfaction.
We merely ask whether this or that object or activity gives us
more or less satisfaction than another. We recognize, moreover,
that different people find satisfaction in different things, and
that the same person who finds satisfaction in one activity today
may find it in quite another tomorrow. None of us permanently
or always chooses "higher" pleasures to "lower"
pleasures, or even vice versa. Even the dedicated ascetic stops
to eat, or to satisfy other bodily needs. And the devotee of Shakespearian
tragedies may relish a good dinner just before he goes to the
theater.
We will return to a fuller discussion of the "pushpin-vs.-poetry"
problem in Chapter 18.
5. Psychological Eudaemonism
I announced at the beginning of this chapter that I would argue
in defense of at least one form of the doctrine of "psychological
eudaemonism."
Some anti-hedonists (of whom I might again cite Hastings Rashdall (11)
as an outstanding example) have adopted what seems a neat way
of disposing of the hedonist contention. They first seek to show
that "psychological hedonism" cannot account
for our real motives in acting. They then point out that while
"ethical hedonism" is still possible, it is slightly
ridiculous to contend that it is one's duty to seek solely
one's own pleasure even if one doesn't always want to.
This refutation itself rests on a series of fallacies, which become
particularly apparent when we abandon the word "pleasure,"
with its special connotations, and instead talk of "satisfaction"
or "happiness."
At the cost of repetition, let us review some of the principal
fallacies in the attack on psychological hedonism:
I. The assumption that "Pleasure" refers only, or
primarily to sensual or carnal pleasure. There is hardly an
anti-hedonist writer who does not at least tacitly make this assumption.
That is why it seems advisable for eudaemonists to abandon the
word "hedonist" and "pleasure" and to speak
instead of "satisfaction' or "happiness." Wherever
we find the word "pleasure" used we must be on guard
against its ambiguity. For it may mean either: (1) sensual pleasure;
or (2) a valued state of consciousness. (13) Or again: "[Hedonism] makes the anticipated
"satisfaction" the condition of the desire, whereas
the desire is really the condition of the satisfaction."
(14)
The contrast here between "desire" and "satisfaction"
is of dubious validity. It is a verbal distinction rather than
a psychological one. It is merely tautological to say that what
I really desire is the satisfaction of my desires. True, I will
not try to satisfy a desire unless I already have the desire.
But it is the satisfaction of the desire, rather than the desire
itself, that I desire! Rashdall's objection comes down to the
triviality that we desire a pleasure only because we desire it.
To say that I seek the satisfaction of my desires is another way
of saying that I desire "happiness," for my happiness
consists in the satisfaction of my desires.
4. Another objection to hedonism is that originating with Bishop
Butler. It declares that what I want is not "pleasure"
but some specific thing. To quote again the sentence cited
a while back: "When I am hungry, I desire food, not pleasure."
We have already pointed out that this merely emphasizes the specific
means by which I seek the satisfaction of a specific desire.
There is no real antithesis here; there is merely a choice between
the concrete and the abstract statement of the situation.
5. Antihedonists seek to discredit psychological hedonism by
pointing out that a man often refuses to take the action that
seems to promise the most immediate or the most intense pleasure.
But this proves nothing at all about psychological hedonism,
and especially not about psychological eudaemonism. It may merely
mean that the man is seeking his greatest pleasure (or satisfaction
or happiness) in the long run. He "measures"
pleasure or satisfaction or happiness by duration as well
as by intensity.
6. The final argument against psychological hedonism or eudaemonism
is that men frequently act under the influence of mere impulse,
passion, or anger and do not do the things calculated to bring
them the maximum of pleasure, satisfaction, or happiness. This
is true. But it remains true that, in his cool moments, it is
his long-run happiness that each man seeks.
Let us restate and summarize this. It is true that men do not
seek to maximize some mere abstraction, some homogeneous juice
called "pleasure." They seek the satisfaction of
their desires. And this is what we mean when we say
that they seek "happiness."
A man's attempted satisfaction of one of his own wishes may conflict
with the satisfaction of another. If, in a moment of impulse or
passion, he attempts to satisfy a merely momentary desire, he
may do so only at the cost of giving up a greater and more enduring
satisfaction. Therefore he must choose among the wishes
he seeks to satisfy; he must seek to reconcile them with the conflicting
wishes of others as well as with his own conflicting wishes. He
must seek, in other words, to harmonize his desires, and
to maximize his satisfactions in the long run.
And this is the reconciliation of psychological and ethical eudaemonism.
A man may not always act in such a way as to maximize his own
long-run happiness. He may be short-sighted or weak-willed, or
the slave of his momentary passions. But he is a psychological
eudaemonist none the less; for, in his cool moments, he does wish
to maximize his own satisfactions or happiness in the long run.
It is because of this that ethical argument may reach and convince
him. If one can successfully point out to him that certain actions,
satisfying some momentary passion, or appearing to promote some
immediate self-interest, will reduce his total satisfactions in
the long run, his reason will accept your argument, and he will
seek to amend his conduct.
This is not necessarily an appeal to mere "egoism."
Most people feel spontaneous sympathy with the happiness and welfare
of others, particularly their family and friends, and would be
incapable of finding much satisfaction or happiness for themselves
unless it were shared by at least those nearest to them, if not
by the community at large. They would seek their own satisfaction
and happiness through acts of kindness and love. Even thoroughly
"selfish" individuals can be brought to see that they
can best promote their own long-run interests through social cooperation,
and that they cannot get the cooperation of others unless they
generously contribute their own.
Even the most self-centered individual, in fact, needing not only
to be protected against the aggression of others, but wanting
the active cooperation of others, finds it to his interest to
defend and uphold a set of moral (as well as legal) rules that
forbid breaking promises, cheating, stealing, assault, and murder,
and in addition a set of moral rules that enjoin cooperation,
helpfulness, and kindness.
Ethics is a means rather than an ultimate end. It has derivative
or "instrumental" value rather than "intrinsic"
or final value. A rational ethics cannot be built merely on what
we "ought" to desire but on what we do desire. Everyone
desires to substitute a more satisfactory state for a less satisfactory
one. As Pascal put it: "Man's ordinary life is like that
of the saints. Both seek satisfaction, and they differ only in
the object in which they set it." Everyone desires his own
long-run happiness. This is true if only because it is tautological.
Our long-run happiness is merely another name for what we do in
fact desire in the long run.
This is the basis not only of the prudential virtues but of the
social virtues. It is in the long-run interest of each of us to
practice the social as well as the prudential virtues and, of
course, to have everyone else practice them.
Here is the answer, and the only persuasive answer, to the question:
"Why should I be moral?" An ought to is always
based upon, and derived from, an is or a will be.
1. John Locke, Essay on Toleration, Book II, Chap. XXI, sec. 40. 2. Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil (London: Oxford University Press, 1907), I, 15. 4. Quoted by Ludwig von Mises, Epistemological Problems of Economics (Princeton: Van Nostrand, 1960), p. 151. Mises' own footnote reference reads: "According to Fr. A. Schmid, quoted by Jodl, Geschichte der Ethil: (2nd ed.), II, 661." 5. Bertrand Russell, Philosophy (New York: Norton, 1927), p. 230. 6. Bertrand Russell, Human Society in Ethics and Politics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1955), pp. 128-130. 7. On "maximization" see Ludwig von Mises, Human Action, pp. 241244. On the possibility of ranking satisfactions, but the impossibility of measuring increases or decreases in happiness or satisfaction, or comparing changes in the satisfaction of different people, see Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State (Princeton: Van Nostrand, 1962), I, 14-17, and I, 436. 8. Utilitarianism (1863), Chap. II. 10. George Santayana, Winds of Doctrine (New York: Scribner's, 1913, 1926), p. 147. 11. The Theory of Good and Evil. See especially I, 7ff. 12. John Hospers (in Human Conduct, pp. 111-121) distinguishes between: ''pleasure]-in the sense of a pleasurable state of consciousness," and pleasure2, "the pleasure derived from bodily sensations." © 1964 Henry Hazlitt. For permissions information, contact The Foundation for Economic Education, 30 South Broadway, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY 10533. Jamie Hazlitt 45 Division St S1 4GE Sheffield, UK +44 114 275 6539 contact@hazlitt.org, / |